Bạn đang xem bản rút gọn của tài liệu. Xem và tải ngay bản đầy đủ của tài liệu tại đây (1.62 MB, 312 trang )
190
THE IMPERMANENT ORGANIZATION
enactment (Weick, 1979, pp. 147–169) as a process was separated from its product,
an enacted environment, to make the point that people are shaped by their own shaping of circumstances. The idea that creations create the creator in organizational life was
elaborated by Weick (2001, pp. 176–236). A typical assertion reads, ‘People act their
way into clearer identities by learning from retrospective interpretations of the improvisations necessary to handle discontinuous work assignments’ (Weick, 2001, p. 177).
That summary sentence includes several properties of organizations that are affected by
organizational designs: prescriptions for action, identities deemed legitimate, climate for
learning, clarity and acceptability of retrospective interpretations, latitude for improvisation, and continuity in work assignments. Under conditions of impermanence all of these
properties assume some form, which then shapes what organized people confront.
In 1995 enactment was repositioned as one of seven properties of sensemaking
(social, identity, retrospect, cues, ongoing, plausibility, enactment) in order to underscore that sensemaking is not simply a matter of idle thought (Weick, 1995). The
insightful work of Mary Parker Follett was added to the growing number of scholars
who described the complexity of enactment. She noted, for example, that:
. . . the activity of the individual is only in a certain sense caused by the stimulus of the
situation because that activity is itself helping to produce the situation which causes
the activity of the individual. . . . My farmer neighbors know this: we prune and graft and
fertilize certain trees, and as our behavior becomes increasingly that of behavior towards
apple-bearing trees, these become increasingly apple-bearing trees. The tree releases
energy in me and I in it; it makes me think and plan and work, and I make it bear edible
fruit. It is a process of freeing on both sides. And this is a creating process (Follett, 1924,
pp. 118–119, cited in Weick, 1995, p. 60).
Chapter 11 continues the elaboration of enactment, this time as part of a point–
counterpoint debate with institutional theorists P. Devereaux Jennings and Royston
Greenwood (2003). If one assumes that cognition lies in the path of the action, then
the question arises as to which cognitions and which actions are salient, legitimate, and
permissible when people organize. The answer from enactment seems to be that any
old cognitions and actions are permissible. That’s nonsense say institutional theorists
and they are right. In Westwood and Clegg’s (2003) words, ‘What institutional theory is
said to add is a rich consideration of context, agency, structure, and mediated causality’
(p. 184). In addition, ‘enactment theory appears to provide a more complete explanation
of the internal worlds and cognitive understandings of the intraorganizational members of
interorganizational systems. Rich ethnography can thus be the appropriate if restricted role
for enactment theory’ (Westwood and Clegg, 2003, p. 184).
The notion of enactment implies more than action. It connotes the creation of structure as in the enactment of regulative legislation. Enactment is about agency ϩ consequences. We do something and the situation is forever changed, and those changes
affect us.
There is no ducking the point that there are times when enactment sounds motivational as well as coolly cognitive. Enactment implies a sort of David and Goliath narrative.
Small wins (Weick, 2001, pp. 426–443) can make a large difference, and sometimes the
CH011.indd 190
7/3/09 12:53:35 AM
ENACTING AN ENVIRONMENT
191
underdog wins. This can sound like naïve whistling in the dark. However, organizational
life, in some of its more gritty moments, is a little like being thrown into someone else’s
mess and then, through enactments, making it your own more orderly mess (p. 197 in
the following reprinted article). In a world connected by weak ties, order writ small need
not stay small.
CH011.indd 191
7/3/09 12:53:36 AM
CH011.indd 192
7/3/09 12:53:36 AM
Enacting an Environment:
The Infrastructure of Organizing
Karl E. Weick
The following article was published as Chapter 6(a) in R. Westwood and
S. Clegg (Eds), Point/Counterpoint: Central Debates in Organisation Theory, London,
Blackwell, 2003, pp. 184–194. Reprinted with permission.
The idea of an enacted environment is a roomy framework in which it is easy to get
tripped up by nouns. For the sake of a point-counterpoint format I want to describe
not so much an “official” version of what enactment might mean, but rather a depiction of what themes it stands for, how it serves to remedy blind spots in organizational
theory, and how it creates its own blind spots. The idea of enactment seems to be useful shorthand, which theorists ignore at their own peril. That claim is the sense in
which the following discussion has a debative quality. But there is more than enough
ignorance to go around, and to act as if anyone formulation has the truth is to drown
in hubris.
Chapter 6(a) unfolds in the following manner. First, I will present a roomy initial
version of what enactment is about, using Nigel Nicholson’s description as the point
of departure. Second, I discuss briefly the context within which the idea of an enacted
environment evolved in order to illustrate that, historically, it synthesized several
salient themes of die 1960s and 1970s. Third, I ground the concept and history of
enactment with a handful of examples. Fourth, I discuss several aspects of the idea
that seem to have staying power because they correct blind spots in theories currently
treated as mainstream. And I conclude by discussing shortcomings in the idea of
enactment.
A Conceptual Delimiting of Enactment
Nigel Nicholson’s (1995) informative entry on enactment in the Encyclopedic Dictionary
of Organizational Behavior provides a solid base from which to begin. He describes
enactment as a concept developed:
to connote an organism’s adjustment to its environment by directly acting upon the environment to change it. Enactment thus has the capacity to create ecological change to
which the organism may have subsequently to adjust . . . [The enactment process is discussed] in the context of active sensemaking by the individual manager or employee . . .
Enactment is thus often a species of self-fulfilling prophecy . . . [Enactment is also about]
the reification of experience and environment through action . . . [The idea] has found
most use in strategic management to capture the dynamics of relations between organization and environment. . . One can expect enactment processes to be most visible in large
and powerful organizations which have market-making capacity, but they are no less relevant to the way smaller enterprises conceive their contexts and make choices about how
they will act in relation to them. (p. 155)
CH011.indd 193
7/3/09 12:53:36 AM
194
KARL E. WEICK
Having touched on most of the key properties of enactment, Nicholson concludes:
As an operational concept, enactment lacks precision and therefore cannot be expected to
be much further elaborated in organizational analysis. However, it embodies an important
recognition of how agency and constructive cognitive processes are essential elements in
our understanding of the behavior of individuals and organizations, (pp. 155–6)
Nicholson catches a number of nuances that are often missed. Enactment is about
both direct and indirect adjustment. Adjustment occurs directly through changing
that which is confronted, and indirectly through changing oneself. Enactment is about
direct action on an environment. Enactment occurs in the context of both organizing
(it is action that induces and is shaped by ecological change) and active sensemaking,
and in both instances resembles the mechanism associated with self-fulfilling prophecies. It is the resemblance to self-fulfilling prophecies that explains why enactment,
which may begin as an expectation embedded in a reification, often has material consequences. The concept seems best suited for strategic management as expressed in
large-scale initiatives deployed by powerful actors. Nevertheless, the idea remains useful to describe activities on a smaller scale as well. Enactment makes it legitimate to
talk about issues of agency and construction in organizational theory, but apparently
at an individual level analysis, as suggested by Nicholson’s reference to enactment by
“an organism,” “the organism,” and “the individual manager and employee.”
Nicholson’s judgment that the concept lacks the precision that would make for further
elaboration is partially weakened by his own evidence that several different properties of
organizing are encoded as a configuration by the word “enactment.” “Precision” may be
less tightly coupled with “susceptibility to elaboration” than is suggested.
But there is an important sense in which Nicholson is right. Some of the “lack of
precision” that concerns him is attributable to the fact that there is an unclear figureground relationship among at least the terms “organizing,” “sensemaking,” and
“enactment.” We see this in Jennings and Greenwood, who, like others, tend to use these
words interchangeably but with some hesitance. I separate these three terms and treat
“organizing” as the modified evolutionary process of ecological change—enactmentselection—retention. These amendments to evolution are spelled out abstractly in 1969
and more organizationally in 1979. Sensemaking, as described in 1995, is not unrelated
to organizing, but it makes a very different point. The seven properties of sensemaking
align with the processes of organizing in a straightforward fashion: ecological change
and enactment in organizing ϭ ongoing updating and enactment in sensemaking;
selection ϭ retrospect, extracted cues; retention ϭ identity, plausibility; feedback from
retention to subsequent enactment and selection ϭ feedback of identity and plausibility
to subsequent enactment and selection. And all of these organizing and sensemaking
events are presumed to be social. The concept of sensemaking differs, however, from
organizing in the sense that it is intended to break the stranglehold that decision making
and rational models have had on organizational theory. Sensemaking implies that key
organizational events happen long before people even suspect that there may be some
kind of decision they have to make. Decision making is incidental, sensemaking is paramount. To focus on decisions is to miss most of what it means to reduce uncertainty and
most of the ways emergent organizing attempts this reduction. Finally, the third concept,
CH011.indd 194
7/3/09 12:53:36 AM
ENACTING AN ENVIRONMENT
195
“enactment,” is the “glue” that joins organizing with sensemaking. Enactment is the
stubborn insistence that people act in order to develop a sense of what they should do
next. Enactment is about two questions: What’s the story? Now what? When people act
in order to answer these questions, their acting typically codetermines the answer. Thus
action alters what people face. It enacts part of their world, even if all that amounts to
is an alteration of themselves. Enactment, at a minimum, changes the actor from inactive to active and, in doing so, deepens the actor’s stake in what is being done and in its
outcome. These are collective, social phenomena between people, not isolated individual
phenomena inside a single head.
Complicated as all of this may appear, it boils down to a straightforward theme: people
are in a complex reciprocal relationship with their environments. The italicized words
emphasize that the referent is collective rather than individual, that causality is mutual
rather than unilateral, and that the circumstances people confront are malleable and
multiple, rather than monolithic and singular.
A Historical Delimiting of Enactment
A deeper understanding of what enactment means may be possible if the idea is situated in the Zeitgeist of the late 1960s, when it was first articulated. The juxtaposition of
the first book-length statement of ethnomethodology (Garfinkel, 1967), an attempt to
synthesize social psychological research on consistency among attitudes and behavior
(e.g. Abelson et al., 1968), a surge of interest in existentialism (e.g., Maclntyre, 1967),
and disenchantment with the passive actor in stimulus-response psychology, all converged on common themes such as action defines cognition, existence precedes essence,
attitudes are draped supportively around prior actions that are tough to undo. Those
themes were heretical in the context of organizational theories that presumed that top
management personified rationality with their enlightened decision making, flawless
forecasting, and omniscient planning.
The convergence in social science around the idea that cognition lies in the path of
the action was not just heretical. It was also prophetic. These ideas coincided with a
growing societal realization that administrators in Washington were trying to justify
committing more resources to a war in Vietnam that the United States was clearly losing. One could not escape the feeling that rationality had a demonstrable retrospective
core, that people looked forward with anxiety and put the best face on it after the fact,
and that the vaunted prospective skills of McNamara’s “whiz kids” in the Pentagon
were a chimera. It was easy to put words to this mess. People create their own fate.
Organizations enact their own environments. The point seemed obvious. What wasn’t
so obvious was the complications this picture created. People resonated to the idea that
they were in control and could have an effect on the world. What they resisted was the
further suggestion that, having changed the world, they had then become the authors
of their own problems. Blaming came full circle, and people now confronted perils of
their own making.
Enactment made sense in and of the 1960s and 1970s when it first appeared. The
debating point is, does enactment still make sense in the circumstances of the new millennium? I think it does, because the basics of organizing, as well as the realities of pervasive
CH011.indd 195
7/3/09 12:53:36 AM
196
KARL E. WEICK
uncertainty, unknowable and unpredictable futures, learning by trial and error, and the
inevitable lag of sensing behind motor actions (I see only what I’ve already done) haven’t
changed that much. The content is different. But the forms through which the content
flows remain pretty much the same.
An Illustrative Delimiting of Enactment
To ground these initial descriptions of enactment, I want to describe some examples.
These examples provide a feel for the phenomenon, suggest scenarios that are tough for
mainstream positions to explain, and serve as templates to spot enactment in other settings. Iatrogenics, physician-induced disease, occurs when diagnostic tests, lines of questioning, or faulty procedures create sickness that was not present when the patient first
consulted with a physician. The physician enacts a sicker and more complicated environment than first confronted him or her. Efforts to lessen the severity of wildland fires
through preventative controlled burns usually (but not always) enact a safer wilderness
for both firefighters and visitors by removing flammable underbrush that can produce
hotter, taller, more explosive fires. An air traffic controller creates a holding pattern by
stacking several aircraft in a small area of air space near a busy airport and, in doing so,
enacts a cluttered display on the radarscope that is more difficult to monitor. Rumors that
a stock trader has an unusually high hit rate often draw attention to that person’s trading, which leads others to duplicate the trader’s pattern of buying, which increases the
action around a stock, which often raises its value, which seems to confirm that
the trader is “hot,” which attracts more buyers and purchases and temporary upticks. The
fact that a bandwagon effect drove up the share price, and not the quality of the stock,
suggests a powerful pathway for enactment in the investment community. Abolafia and
Kilduff ’s (1988) fascinating reconstruction of attempts to corner the silver market show
in detail the ways in which enactment in financial markets can build on itself. NASA
enacts a lean, mean environment in which overworked employees fail to convert metric units into the same units of measurement used in the rest of the project. As a result,
an entire mission fails in public view, credibility is questioned, and whatever “savings”
were gained through lean operation are lost in irretrievable hardware and the addition
of time-consuming damage control. When Mercedes-Benz merges with Chrysler, and
Travelers merges with Citibank, these so-called “mergers of equals” administered by coCEOs enact an acquisition of unequals in which the stronger CEO consolidates his (all
four CEOs were male) initial advantage and soon ends on top. Hospitals refuse to report
medical mistakes for fear of losing business and in their refusals enact new suspicions
that keep away the very people they feared they would lose by disclosure. Proctor &
Gamble initiate merger talks that enact shareholder flight from the stock, which drives
down both share price and P&G’s attractiveness as a merger partner. Organizations that
encourage closeness to the client enact a permissive world that encourages outrageous
customer demands that can be remedied only by firing the client they tried so hard to
recruit. An arrogant management team from the Union Pacific Railroad fires personnel from the newly acquired Southern Pacific Railroad and in doing so loses expertise
needed to run the tricky railyard in Houston, manage to gridlock not only the yard but
the southwest region, paralyze infuriated shippers, and create a lingering suspicion
CH011.indd 196
7/3/09 12:53:37 AM
ENACTING AN ENVIRONMENT
197
of the entire railroad industry. Campaign contributions enact a more selective administration of regulative environments. Successful lobbying of Congress to start daylight saving time earlier in the year increases hours of daylight in the spring and sales of garden
supplies climb, but sales of candy at Hallowe’en plummet because people are unwilling
to go trick-or-treating in the dark.
So what do physicians, firefighters, air traffic controllers, traders, aerospace engineers, CEOs, hospital administrators, and lobbyists demonstrate? They show that discretion and strategic choice, implemented in ongoing work, can change the conditions
of that work. They show that individual work can enact conditions that other people
and other systems have to cope with. For example, iatrogenic disease does not stop
at the physician’s door as the newly troubled patient walks out. Instead, the altered
patient walks into the medical care system, where the consequences of the initial treatment spread and where the patient’s problems with the physician become other people’s problems as well. Enactment creates contingencies as well as events. The initiating
conditions seem small in comparison to macro events only because these examples
articulate the local turning point, the point of bifurcation, the moment of initiation.
These triggering moments often serve to implant small but uncontained outcomes in
larger systems. These embedded, uncontained outcomes continue to grow undetected
until they spawn unanticipated consequences that threaten legitimacy, competence,
and control. In each of the examples it is also important to note that the actors are
not passive. They do not simply scan or notice or detect or perceive or sense the environment. Instead, they probe the circumstances into which they have been thrown.
These probes are not blind, since experience, socialization, job descriptions, and culture influence them. These influences are relative, however, in the sense that they still
leave considerable latitude. People still act with discretion, often with only a vague idea
of what they are doing and what effect it will have. Their discretionary acting is intertwined with what they sense, although it is rare for busy actors to sort out the relative
contributions. But whether actors reflect on their creations or not, analysts need to be
mindful that organizational environments are not just an occasion for selective perception. They are also an occasion for selective intervention and shaping. Thus to change
an organization is not simply to change what people notice, but how they notice. Active
noticing leaves traces. Those enacted traces are drawn up into systems as problems for
others. Thus any attempt to increase effectiveness will fail if all it tries to affect is what
people notice, and not what they do as well.
Presumptions of an Enactment Perspective
But what does an enactment perspective enable people to see and say about organizations that they miss when they invoke the modern trinity of transaction costs,
institutional theory, and population ecology (TIP)? One thing enactment does is that it
buys conceptual flexibility. (One man’s “imprecision” is another man’s “roominess.”) All
three of the current mainstream positions make sense only so long as we presume that
stasis rather than dynamics are what we need to explain, that reification of an invisible hand is a legitimate conceptual move, that everyday interacting and conversing
are inconsequential, that there is an ontological difference between macro and micro
CH011.indd 197
7/3/09 12:53:38 AM
198
KARL E. WEICK
levels of analysis, that people tell the truth when they fill out survey instruments or
make entries in archival records, and that people are not distracted, preoccupied,
or careless when they evaluate their options, try to follow precedent, or get thrown into
the middle of someone else’s mess.
Enactment helps people see constructive activity as well as maintenance and routine, because it is about verbs. Enactment is about operants, acts that operate on the
world. It is about a set of words such as efferent, impose, project, shape, proact, control, manage, and establish, all of which imply agency or acting one’s intentions into
the world. Enacting is visible in emerging organizational structures, redesign, and
reorganizing. The conversation analyst Deirdre Boden (1994) illustrates this emphasis
nicely in her description of the foundational nature of turn taking as a structure in
organizing. For her, the organization becomes a real and practical place:
only as the consequence of a recurrently generated ongoing conversation, multiply laminated, a world of telephone calls, meetings, planning sessions, sales talks and corridor
conversations by means of which people inform, amuse, update, gossip, review, reassess,
reason, instruct, revise, argue, debate, contest and actually constitute the moments, myths
and through time, the very structuring of the organization . . . [T]he structuring properties of turn-taking provide the fine, flexible interactional system out of which institutional
relations and institutions themselves are conjured turn by turn . . . The business of talk
in the technical sense, is thereby transformed into business that gets done through talk.
(Excerpted from Taylor and Van Every, 2000: 220)
To enact a conversational environment, close in, is to breach or bend the orderliness
of turn taking. To enact opportunities and constraints into organizing is to interrupt a
partner who is talking, to stay silent, to ignore, to affirm without warning, to attend,
to mitigate, to reconcile, to cancel, or to close. Acts like these transform social circumstances into novel conversational texts, and these texts then provide an enacted platform
for further action.
Enactment helps people see the environment as something other than resources,
institutional precedents, promises, uninterpreted information, niches, models to mimic,
markets, liabilities, and costs. The “something other” is that all of those preceding features are names, punctuations, and interpretations imposed in the interest of meaning.
If one is puzzled, then “finding” an organization to mimic, an institutional guideline
to follow, a resource to be hoarded, a market to be saturated, or a liability to be skirted
are ways to make sense and allocate effort. What makes any one of these quite diverse
punctuations plausible is that they are imposed on circumstances that amount to
a pun. People in organizations notice circumstances precisely because something unexpected occurs or something expected fails to occur (Mandler, 1982; Heidegger, 1962;
Louis and Sutton, 1991). How one acts in the face of puns influences what will have
been seen and done. For example, the bridge crew on a ship running at night, who are
unable to agree whether another ship ahead of them is moving toward them or away
from them, by their own actions enact the traffic they face. By positioning their own
ship based on the erroneous assumption that the ship in front is moving away from
them, that they are overtaking it, and that they should pass it on its port side, they
change the relationship between the two ships. This change now enacts a pun for the
CH011.indd 198
7/3/09 12:53:38 AM
ENACTING AN ENVIRONMENT
199
oncoming other ship. (That ship looks like it is passing us both on our starboard and on
our port.) As the ships, which are actually coming toward each other, close faster and
take “evasive” action based on opposite views of what is unfolding, they steer into one
another (Perrow, 1984). What began as an equivocal pun for one party – a ship ahead
with an equivocal pattern of running lights that could mean either that it is coming
or going and that we should meet it by passing either right or left – becomes a pun for
the other party, and ends with the clarity of a collision. The issue is not decision making. The issue is what people thought they faced, a perception that was clarified by the
actions they took, what those actions made salient, and the repertoire of interpretations
available to them as a result of past experience and their current conversations.
The point here is simply that more than perception is involved. Perceptually, the crew
faced an equivoque. Their actions to resolve the indeterminacy produced a more determinate environment. The fact that the determinate environment led to bad outcomes
is not the only issue. Equally important is the issue of what happened on the input side.
How did people develop a sense of what they faced, what prevented their updating of
that initial sense, how did their own actions affect their sense of certainty, how much
of the data remained outside their explanation, and what were they doing while all of
this happened? Questions like these are common when the world is treated as an indeterminate place that people make more sensible by acting their way into it. An indeterminate world is not a random world. Instead, it is loosely coupled, amenable to multiple
interpretations, malleable to action, and contingent. Indeterminacy means differentially
determinant, an “obvious” partition being that technology and other material artifacts
are more determinant than are social resources. I put quotation marks around “obvious” because the world does not often sort itself neatly into those two categories. Latour
(1988) has made this clear in his insistence that the pairing of tools with people does
not create an aggregate. Instead, it creates a fused hybrid that is unified through action,
a hybrid similar to what Heidegger seems to have in mind when he describes readyto-hand being.
The discussion up to this point is noteworthy in the sense that it illustrates a third
way in which enactment captures what the big three miss. The typical referent in most
discussions of enactment tends to be small: the dyad, the small group, the double interact, the conversation, the principal-agent relationship, the imagined other, the individual, the team, face-to-face interaction, the partner, the confidant, and the co-leader.
Units of this size tend to be lumped together as a micro level of analysis and then dismissed as inconsequential in a world of large organizations, substantial power distance,
tall hierarchies, top management teams, interlocking directorates, scripts and routines,
outsourced work, organizational fields, alliances, webs, and cultures. Regardless of the
imagery, it is common to separate the organization as entity from individuals as its components. Having done so, investigators then argue that communication occurs in the
container of an organization, or that the organization is produced by communication,
and therefore can stand alone once communication stops. It is less common to read that
organizations emerge in communication and are shaped momentarily by the nature
of the relationship and the forms in the language that are realized when organizing is
talked and acted into existence.
This is a long-standing issue that keeps getting lost on people who reify large arbitrary
assortments of people into acting entities. The issue is whether macro and micro are
CH011.indd 199
7/3/09 12:53:38 AM
200
KARL E. WEICK
distinct entities. The answer from enactment is that there is no ontological difference
between micro and macro, a position that is also articulated by Giddens and Latour
(Taylor and Van Every, 2000: 141–72). Organization is realized in moments of conversation and joint action that are embedded in day-to-day interactions. Conversation
is the site of organizational emergence, and the text generated during the conversation, its surface (Taylor and Van Every, 2000). Thus what an organization will have
become is a property of communication and is read from the conversing. Said differently, organization is talked into existence again and again through conversations that
overlap in time and space. Plausible summaries of these conversations that give conversants an identity, and their conversations some coherence, are fed back to participants
by macro-actors. These moments of enunciation, which enable people to see what they
have said and what it might amount to, occur when macro-actors (people who act on
behalf of distributed conversations) are doing such things as writing an annual report,
holding a press conference, issuing an order to employees, arguing for a position in the
senior management committee, writing an internal report, talking employees into a
strike, writing a column for an influential business publication, and so on (Taylor, personal communication, May 21, 2000).
There are constraints on enactment just as there are constraints on the big three. But
the constraints on enactment are lodged in quite different places. There are constraints
in the grammar of the language that is used to convert interaction into text, constraints in the discipline of interaction, and constraints in the texts that are reflexively
treated as evidence that shared images are being produced, accepted, and elaborated.
To take the big three seriously is to translate their mechanisms into language, interaction, and shared images, and to pinpoint where and how they get talked into existence.
Enactment thrives quite well without a macro/micro split. It does not waste time trying
to, first, separate the organization as entity from the individual as component, and then,
second, reconnect them. The economy of enactment lies in its treatment of organization as a form of social life that is:
invariably situated, circumstantial, and locally realized in a finite time and place involving
real people . . . [M]anagerial interventions are not exogenous at all, but merely another
locally realized, personally communicated act expressed in language (a speech act), with
this special characteristic, that they are meant to be, and are treated as being, declarative
[declarative = communication that causes a state of affairs to exist, e.g. a priest saying, “I
declare you man and wife,” marries the couple]. (Taylor and Van Every, 2000, p. 143)
Portraits of organization that posit autonomous structures, interorganizational relationships, and populations as containers filled with reactive individuals are convenient
fictions behind which the containing gets worked out and changed through acting,
conversing, and textualizing. Continuities in framing, in action, and in language from
conversation to conversation, coupled with adjustments on the spot to the vagaries of
interaction, produce distributed understanding that is more intelligent than is evident
in any one conversation (Weick and Roberts, 1993). When macro-actors feed portions
of this understanding back to the conversationalists, the feedback enables the conversationalists to talk organization into existence more readily and more prominently. The
idea that organizations as well as environments are enacted is missing from many discussions of enactment, although not from those of Giddens and Latour. If conversation
CH011.indd 200
7/3/09 12:53:38 AM