Bạn đang xem bản rút gọn của tài liệu. Xem và tải ngay bản đầy đủ của tài liệu tại đây (4.19 MB, 670 trang )
162
Handbook of Public Policy Analysis
only the current consensus—sometimes very long-lived—within a community of researchers. Thus
science has a communicative context, and scientific knowledge claims are contingent.
Science is an elite enterprise that systematically excludes or marginalizes incompetent practitioners. Scientific norms, practices of peer review, and credentialing institutions all work to filter
out poorly trained and less talented researchers, although these arrangements can also encourage
a stifling orthodoxy. Democracy, it is worth noting, also has elements of exclusivity—madmen,
children, and noncitizens do not vote (Guston 1993). Yet it remains true that only a tiny segment
of society produces, communicates, and advocates on behalf of the scientific knowledge used in
public decision making. Its moral autonomy has “helped create science in an Old Testament style,
that is, respect without comprehension” (Toumey 1996, 34).
There are other sources of relevant, elite-based knowledge. The legal expertise of attorneys,
the moral authority of religious leaders, the sharp pencils of accountants, and the contributions of
many types of professionals all might contribute to better public decision making.
Difficulties emerge when deciding whose knowledge counts the most. Citizens vary in their
education, life experience, raw intelligence, and particular knowledge. It makes sense to delegate
certain decisions to experts. We ask engineers to design our bridges, neurosurgeons to operate on
our brains, and economists to set monetary policy. Yet sometimes the value of elite expertise is less
clear. Thus toxicological knowledge may be no more relevant than local fishing lore when setting
fish consumption advisories in polluted waters. Experts also have limited domains of expertise, so
it is not clear whether a biologist or a priest has a stronger claim in helping politicians decide the
ethics of embryonic stem cell research. Some scientific knowledge is uncertain or irrelevant, some
relevant knowledge is local rather than general, and some decisions turn on values as much as on
the facts.
SUBSTANTIVE AND PROCEDURAL DIMENSIONS
Simon (1976) offers one solution to the dilemma of whose knowledge counts by distinguishing between substantive and procedural rationality. He measures substantive rationality relative to optimal
outcomes, and procedural rationality relative to optimal decision processes.
Scientifically produced knowledge contributes to substantive rationality. Such knowledge describes phenomena and explains causal factors. It provides the factual basis for better decisions. It
satisfies scientific criteria of validity and reliability, and it justifies authoritative knowledge claims.
Scientific knowledge is a key input that contributes to the “best” outcome.
Yet every decision also has a procedural component: Who makes the decision, and what are the
prescribed steps in making the decision? Procedural rationality helps improve decisions by specifying
their “who” and “how” aspects. Optimal processes are legitimate, reasoned, and transparent.
Simon’s distinction between substantive and procedural rationality maps nicely onto a distinction made decades earlier by Weber (1922) regarding sources of legitimacy. Public decisions are
legitimate if they are legal, authoritative, and appropriate for the context. There are two very different
sources of legitimacy. First, there is the legitimacy of authority, based in status, as enjoyed by divine
rulers, revered elders, and scientific experts. Second, there is the legitimacy of consent, based in civil
society, and deriving from following constitutional rules and open, democratic procedures. These
distinctions make intuitive sense, but they also raise a troubling question: Are these two sources of
legitimacy complementary or does one displace the other? Symmetrically, does increased procedural
rationality come at the expense of decreased substantive rationality?
Lindblom (1990) argues forcefully that substantive rationality should not be allowed to displace
procedural rationality. Especially regarding social phenomena, he doubts that science ever rises
above mere confirmation of common sense. He believes that social scientific expertise should not
Fisher_DK3638_C012.indd 162
10/16/2006 10:49:00 AM
Rationality in Policy Decision Making
163
be privileged over lay judgment in public decision making, and he advocates a self-guided rather
than a scientifically guided society. Science should play only a minor supporting role. Lindblom’s
argument draws strongly on his famous “muddling through” conception, which asserts that scientific planning frequently fails in decentralized capitalist democracies because power is shared and
no one has full information (1959). His solution is to encourage incrementalism in policy-making,
and continual, mutual adjustment among policy actors.
Critics of Lindblom assert that incrementalism is the rational procedure sometimes but not all
of the time (Breheny and Hooper 1985; Smith and May 1980). There are decisions in which expert
contributions to substantive rationality are essential, such as the bridge-building example mentioned
earlier. There are also “big” decisions that cannot be easily or cheaply reversed or subdivided, such as
damming a major river, starting a nuclear power plant, or going to war. In such cases, the goodness
of decisions depends equally on their procedural and substantive elements. However, the critics face
a daunting task in explaining which decisions should be incremental and which should not.
RATIONAL AND REASONABLE
There is a way to relieve some of the inconsistencies identified in the preceding paragraphs, by
distinguishing between decision making and analysis. Decision making is the art of choosing reasonable decision rules, ones that are appropriate for each decision context. Reasonable decision rules
are internally consistent and an outcome of moral argumentation, they are values-based. Analysis is
the science of applying those decision rules rationally, according to appropriate standards. Rational
analysis is logical, valid, reliable, and empirically tested, it is fact-based. Values and facts are distinct
intellectual categories although they can be hard to distinguish from one another in practice.
“Irrational” decisions are often nothing more than the rational application of unreasonable
decision rules. For example, given a “net social benefit” decision rule, it may seem quite rational to
dam a major river like the Yangtze. If a “no losers” test had been applied instead, then the rational
choice might be to leave the river alone. Rationality in policy decision making thus requires both
reasonable decision rules and rational applications of those rules.
Often the jobs of analysis and decision making are separated because of the scale and complexity of modern society. This opens up the possibility that analysts will not check with decision
makers to determine which decision rule is reasonable. Equally, decision makers may not bother
to check with analysts regarding the rationality of the rule’s particular application. Rationality in
policy decision making thus depends crucially on effective communication between decision makers and analysts.
The troubling word “appropriate” appears twice in this section, raising difficult questions. How
does a decision maker know that a decision rule is reasonable, that is, appropriate to its context?
Also, how does an analyst know that the logical and empirical standards applied are rational, that is,
appropriate to the decision rule and its context? The answer to both questions is that appropriateness
is socially determined. Both decision makers and analysts thus must communicate with others—the
population at large as well as a range of experts—to confirm that they have acted appropriately.
SINGLE AND MULTIPLE DECISION MAKERS
Some decisions seem private: you choose your breakfast items, your day’s clothes, and whether to
get out of bed in the morning. Yet even despots do not get to make truly independent decisions. If
you know that others strongly influence your own choice of food, clothing, and schedule, you also
suspect that even Adolf Hitler and Julius Caesar needed to consult with confidantes and mollify the
Fisher_DK3638_C012.indd 163
10/16/2006 10:49:00 AM
164
Handbook of Public Policy Analysis
masses. Almost all policy decisions are truly multi-party decisions. This implies, first, that there
must be a procedural component to public decision making that specifies how the parties interact.
Second, this multi-party context implies that communication among parties will strongly influence
outcomes.
As the next section illustrates, a close look at the tools of rational policy analysis shows that
some of the most widely used methods blithely assume a single omniscient decision maker. For
example, a hypothetical social planner acts on behalf of the whole population when selecting socially
optimal policies by means of benefit-cost analysis. The risk assessor likewise weighs expected aggregate social risks and benefits when selecting optimal regulations. Such tools simplify away the
procedural and communicative challenges of public decision making. We need to move beyond
them (Andrews 2002).
TOOLS OF RATIONAL POLICY ANALYSIS
The science of public decision making has in fact evolved rapidly over the past century. A quick
tour spanning welfare maximization, public choice, multi-agent simulation, and decision support
follows.
WELFARE MAXIMIZATION
Starting from a microeconomic notion of individual utility, rationally pursued, Bergson, later extended by Samuelson, developed an additive social welfare function, with optimal public policy being
that which maximizes the aggregate utility across members of the population. This individualistic
formulation contrasts with competing concepts such as Benthamite utility (“the greatest good for
the greatest number”).
Benefit-cost analysis is a widely used tool that attempts to guide policymakers to welfare-maximizing choices. At its heart is the Kaldor-Hicks decision criterion that directs the “social planner”
to choose the alternative providing the greatest net social benefits. It depends on two very strong
assumptions, first, that it is reasonable to add gains and losses across individuals when calculating
the societal net benefit; and, second, that the things individuals gain or lose are easily substitutable
so that the winners can, at least hypothetically, compensate the losers. Thus it offers substantive
equivalence to the Pareto criterion that underlies the microeconomic conception of free markets,
because both can yield efficient outcomes.
However, the Pareto criterion also has a procedural component that promotes fairness as well
as efficiency: it requires unanimous and voluntary participation in transactions to ensure that decisions have no losers, only mutual gains. The Kaldor-Hicks criterion is more procedurally coercive,
implying majority rule at best, and dictatorship by the social planner at worst. Yet, realistically,
many things that civilizations need impose costs on a few in order to reap broad social benefits.
Examples include public education, progressive income taxation, highways, power plants, sewage
treatment plants, and jails.
Benefit-cost analysis thus has a place in the policy analysis toolkit. As a decision aid, it is
teachable, replicable, quantitative, and offers progressive insights that help narrow choices. Done
properly, it requires a comprehensive enumeration of costs and benefits—this is both a strength and
a weakness, since comprehensiveness is technically impossible even if it is conceptually desirable.
Practitioners have attempted to include an ever-broader range of tangible, intangible, and temporally
distant costs and benefits.
Fisher_DK3638_C012.indd 164
10/16/2006 10:49:00 AM
Rationality in Policy Decision Making
165
PUBLIC CHOICE
The microeconomic approach has led to a variety of contributions under the rubric of public choice
theory that show how individual interests influence both marketplace and public policy outcomes.
Self-interested bureaucratic actors maximize their budgets (Niskanen 1971), and citizens form clubs
to collectively provide some forms of public goods (Buchanan 1965), for example. The plausibility of social welfare functions has been challenged by Arrow (1951) on logical grounds, because
under reasonable assumptions it is possible to show that any democratic aggregation process leads
to inconsistent and unstable results.
Our collective decision-making mechanisms are deeply flawed, so that neither markets nor
politics on their own serve us adequately. Markets are sometimes inequitable because they concentrate wealth while making one dollar equal one economic vote, and because future generations get
no votes. Also, market imperfections abound, with monopoly power, public goods, externalities,
and information problems being the most severe weaknesses. Government failures also abound.
Bureaucratic self-interest can encourage agents within government to maximize their budgets or
allow regulatory agencies to be captured. Also, as discussed earlier, democratic decision making
according to “reasonable” criteria can become arbitrary and unstable (Arrow 1951). Given criteria
of collective rationality, a Pareto (no losers) principle, independence of irrelevant alternatives,
and non-dictatorship, Arrow presents an impossibility theorem for the existence of social welfare
functions. He shows that pairwise voting such as is currently practiced in most elections leads to
endless cycling, majority rule can select no winner non-arbitrarily, society’s preferences do not
exhibit collective rationality and do not aggregate individual preferences consistently, and that by
not counting the intensity of preferences, voting will lead to inconsistent outcomes (Pearce 1986).
Formal democratic decision-making mechanisms thus need to be supplemented sometimes.
One solution is to relax some of Arrow’s reasonable criteria. By relaxing the Pareto postulate, we open up the solution domain to allow winners, losers, and compensation. By relaxing the
independence postulate, we move from pairwise comparisons to multiple options. By relaxing the
unlimited domain postulate (part of collective rationality), we allow efforts to foster unanimity
prior to a vote. We maintain transitivity (the other part of collective rationality) and nondictatorship.
Public participation is one way to relax Arrow’s criteria while preserving elements of democracy,
as will be discussed shortly.
There have been many important extensions to the microeconomic approach that have broadened its reach. Game theorists have usefully characterized responses to governmental interventions
as mixed-motive (competitive-cooperative) negotiations (Axelrod 1984). Decision theorists have
introduced concepts of risk preference and multi-criteria tradeoffs (Keeney and Raiffa 1976),
thereby forcing into daylight the issues of risk and priority associated with policies. Psychologists
have demonstrated that individuals rely on heuristics and suffer from systematic biases that are
not reflected in standard utility functions (Tversky and Kahneman 1974), thereby weakening the
policy optimality claims of microeconomic analysts, and highlighting the roles of communication
and perception in public management. Most of these contributions have the effect of making the
science more effective in describing, explaining, and prescribing changes in public decision making,
in accord with an individualistic, utilitarian form of rationality.
Modern microeconomic theory now explicitly acknowledges both the independence and interdependence of decision makers. Theory now has much to say about the importance of rules and
access to information, pinpointing conditions leading to stable, efficient, and (sometimes) equitable
outcomes. Equally important, an emerging emphasis on collection of experimental evidence has
made microeconomics a more realistic behavioral science.
Fisher_DK3638_C012.indd 165
10/16/2006 10:49:00 AM
166
Handbook of Public Policy Analysis
MULTI-AGENT SIMULATION
Multi-agent simulation is a relatively new modeling approach that seeks to generalize from microeconomic game theory by incorporating more actors, imbuing them with more realistic cognitive
limitations in the form of bounded rationality and imperfect knowledge, and investigating out-ofequilibrium conditions. Access to cheap computing power has allowed modelers to explore cases
that used to be mathematically intractable, involving heterogeneous actors, evolutionary processes,
and emergent structural relationships. In policy simulations, preferred governmental interventions
sometimes diverge dramatically from those identified as optimal under neoclassical microeconomic
assumptions.
The multi-agent approach has been useful in the innovation, anti-trust, environmental, and
security policy domains, among others (Axelrod 1997; Barnett et al. 2000; Epstein and Axtell 1996;
Gilbert and Troitzch 1999). One early application shows how a widespread individual preference
for having as few as one-third of your neighbors share your own ethnicity will lead to highly segregated housing patterns, even in the absence of discriminatory real estate market actors and policies
(Schelling 1978). Another application shows how modeling with adaptive agents can yield results
that are at variance with those of neoclassical economics. In particular, in perfectly competitive
markets, regulation is either distorting and inefficient or irrelevant. However, when agents—firms
in this model—are heterogeneous, boundedly rational, and interact directly with one another out of
equilibrium, regulations can be demonstrated to have positive welfare effects (Teitelbaum 1998).
DECISION SUPPORT SYSTEMS
Another important innovation has been to reframe policy analysis as a decision support activity
rather than a surrogate for actual decision making. The distinction is important. Traditional policy
analysis accepts a request for a study from the decision makers, sets the scope of the research question, establishes key assumptions, carries out the analysis, and delivers policy recommendations
back to the decision makers. Decision support systems instead reserve key decisions for decision
makers, and plan for repeated interactions between analysts and decision makers. It is a humbler
approach but its analytics are often more complex.
An example of a decision support system is a regional electric power planning tool used a
few years ago in New England (Andrews 1992). Its purpose was to help break an impasse among
utility companies, regulators, environmentalists, and other interested parties regarding public utility investment policy. Analysts built a complex scenario analysis tool for simulating the operation
of the regional power system under various assumptions over a multi-decade time horizon, and
then they convened a planning process that involved all of these parties. Iteratively, the analysts
proposed the scope of analysis and the stakeholders approved it, the analysts offered assumptions
for review and the stakeholders approved them, when stakeholders disagreed among themselves
about certain assumptions the analysts ran their model both ways and reported back whether their
answers diverged, the stakeholders suggested policy alternatives and the analysts evaluated their
multi-attribute impacts, the stakeholders evaluated these simulated impacts and drew their own
conclusions about which solution was optimal from their point of view, and out of this interaction
emerged broad consensus on a new set of energy policies for the region. Decision support systems
have found application in an increasing number of fields spanning urban planning, environmental
policy, health policy, energy policy, international relations, and military policy, among others (Sauter
1997; Brail and Klosterman 2001).
Readers will detect that the key distinction between traditional policy analysis and decision
support systems is that the latter have an explicit procedural component. Decision support analysts
Fisher_DK3638_C012.indd 166
10/16/2006 10:49:00 AM
Rationality in Policy Decision Making
167
devote much effort to mapping the points in a decision process at which analysts might helpfully
intervene. They then apply themselves to the design of potentially fruitful interactions at those few
key points. They are shifting the practice of policy analysis away from a major focus on substantive
rationality to giving equal consideration to procedural rationality.
In sum, the tools of rational policy analysis have evolved over a century toward a richer conception of rationality that acknowledges substantive and procedural dimensions, rational applications
of reasonable decision rules, an expectation that interested parties hold diverse views, and more
limited roles for experts. These tools must appropriately blend facts and values as they produce
actionable policy advice.
PUBLIC PARTICIPATION
Public participation has several potential roles in policy decision making, and the reasons offered
for encouraging it are diverse (Wengert 1976). One can pursue participation as policy, that is, with a
normative perception that it is desirable in and of itself because, in the words of Susskind and Elliott
(1983), it democratizes, decentralizes, deprofessionalizes, and demystifies public policy. One can
pursue participation as a strategy, as a means for achieving other ends. Participation can operate as
communication, leading to improved information flows that produce better decisions. Participation
can serve as therapy, a way to coopt alienated groups into the mainstream. It can function as conflict
resolution, so that participation may (or may not) lead to reduced tensions and stable outcomes in
controversial decisions. More intuitively, the best way to find out what people want and value is to
ask them (Feiveson et al. 1976).
There is a spectrum of participation mechanisms available (FEARO 1988):
•
•
•
•
•
•
Public information (ads, newsletters, exhibits)
Public information feedback (polls, focus groups, surveys)
Consultation (hearings, workshops, panels, games)
Extended involvement (advisory committees, charrettes, task forces)
Joint planning (arbitration, conciliation, mediation, negotiation, partnership)
Delegation (citizen control, home rule)
Choosing which mode of participation to solicit is important because each has distinctive
strengths and weaknesses. Steps in choosing a mechanism typically include informal early consultation to identify major issues and actors, confirmation of an organizational mandate to proceed in an
accountable and open fashion, identification of potentially interested participants including those
who are unlikely to receive representation, analysis of the specific situation, setting objectives for
the participation process, determining information exchange requirements, planning the length of
the activity and the complexity of involvement, implementation, and evaluation of how it worked
(FEARO, 1988).
Cultivating public participation as a conscious strategy or policy does not mean that it may
not arise “naturally” in spontaneous occurrences. The existing pattern of public interaction sets the
stage. Susskind and Elliott (1988) describe patterns of paternalism (elites govern, they inform the
public of decisions), conflict (members of the public begin to distrust the elites, they second-guess
decisions and demand participation), and coproduction (elites and members of the public share
decision-making power and constructively resolve conflicts).
Like other collective decision-making mechanisms, public participation also has flaws. These
include potential tyranny of the majority or minority, instability of decisions, poor information,
apathy and stakeholder fatigue, adverse reactions to perfunctory involvement, and the nonrepresentativeness of participants in any small group process.
Fisher_DK3638_C012.indd 167
10/16/2006 10:49:01 AM
168
Handbook of Public Policy Analysis
In evaluating the success of public participation processes, Webler and Renn (1995) argue
that the key criteria are fairness and competence. A fair process gives all interested parties equal
opportunities to participate in the discourse, make validity claims, challenge validity claims made
by others, and determine when closure is reached. A competent process operates in direct tension
with fairness, however, by setting minimal standards for cognitive and lingual competence, ensuring reliance on appropriate knowledge, using a consensually approved translation scheme, and
relying on the most reliable methodological techniques available. In addition to balancing fairness
and competence, traditional measures of effectiveness and value also figure into perceived success.
Participation increases the rationality of public decision making to the extent that it overcomes the
failings of markets and politics, as well as its own internal weaknesses.
THEORETICAL AND PRACTICAL REASON
Philosophers identify theoretical and practical reason as two distinct approaches to the facts-values
dichotomy in public decision making. Theoretical reason is the rationality underlying pure science,
and it helps us evaluate whether our theories have empirical validity. Practical reason is the rationality underlying decision making, and it helps us evaluate the normative validity of our actions.
Marrying facts and values—analysis and decision making—requires integrating theoretical and
practical reason.
Is such a marriage necessary or even desirable? Perhaps only one type of reason is enough.
Theoretical reason, for example, is a consequentialist, outcome-oriented doctrine that prizes usefulness in linking facts and values. For its disciples, good science generates testable hypotheses and
credible data that usefully advance knowledge, and good decision making leads to useful, utilityenhancing outcomes.
Practical reason, by contrast, is a deontological, obligation-oriented doctrine that prizes wide
acceptance in linking facts and values. For its disciples, good science produces widely accepted
knowledge, and good decision making is also widely accepted.
Unfortunately, neither theoretical nor practical reason offers truly universal lessons. Theoretical
reason delivers only temporary truths because science is always contingent. Practical reason delivers only useful norms because experience is never adequate to support the formulation of absolute
moral laws. Both doctrines offer plausible ways to integrate facts and values in decision making,
as long as one is willing to accept an extremely limited, relative form of rationality.
INSTRUMENTAL, STRATEGIC, AND COMMUNICATIVE RATIONALITY
Jantsch (1975) points out that different contexts demand different rationalities. When the task is
simply to rationalize the use of scarce resources in the absence of uncertainty or conflict, an instrumental response is appropriate. Instrumental rationality optimizes the allocation of resources
according to an efficiency criterion. For example, a public works manager operates instrumentally
to allocate a fixed budget among pipes, valves, filters, pumps, concrete, excavation equipment, and
labor when designing a water supply system.
When the task is to rationalize a set of steering principles for managing uncertainty and complexity, a strategic response is appropriate. Strategic rationality optimizes strategies for responding
to change induced at least partly by the actions of others, according to an effectiveness criterion.
For example, a mayor operates strategically when deciding whether to build a water supply system
ahead of or in response to demand, even as developers and prospective residents decide whether to
build and buy new homes in her city.
Fisher_DK3638_C012.indd 168
10/16/2006 10:49:01 AM
Rationality in Policy Decision Making
169
When the task is to rationalize a set of collective preferences—norms—for managing conflict,
then a communicative response is appropriate. Communicative rationality optimizes opportunities
for achieving consensus, according to a criterion of ethical behavior. For example, the mayor may
ask a municipal planning commission to develop, in consultation with stakeholders and the general
public, a widely accepted land use plan that represents the community’s vision of where and when
future development will happen, including any required water supply system improvements.
A devotee of theoretical reason, say, a utilitarian, will respond instrumentally in a non-social
context and strategically in a social, multi-party context. This person will test the validity of scientific
facts by considering the empirical evidence. She will test the validity of decision-making values by
confirming that her utility increases.
A devotee of practical reason, by contrast, will respond instrumentally in a non-social context
but she will act communicatively in a social, multi-party context. She will test the validity of both
facts and values with reference to the degree of consensus each enjoys.
So, in a non-social context, devotees of both theoretical and practical reason operate instrumentally. But in a social context—which is far more prevalent—there is divergence because a theoretical
reasoner will operate strategically and a practical reasoner will operate communicatively (see Table
12.1). Thus, if the mayor is a theoretical reasoner, she will extend her town’s water supply system
strategically, seizing opportunities as they arise, without consultation, and maximizing her own
expected benefits along the way. On the other hand, if she is a practical reasoner, the mayor will
operate in a more deliberative manner, seeking broad input and acceptance of the water system’s
expansion plans and ensuring that neither she nor developers and residents are blind-sided by any
aspect of the development process.
Such an argument overstates the differences, however, because there can be utilitarian reasons
to operate communicatively. First, conflict can be a source of scarcity and uncertainty, giving communication both instrumental and strategic value. Second, the contingent and socially constructed
nature of scientific knowledge implies communication challenges, and highlights the value of
achieving consensus on “serviceable facts.” Third, since every public decision has a procedural
component, interested parties will have opportunities to reward conformance with widely shared
norms of ethical behavior. Fourth, the contemporary common division of labor between analysts
and decision makers can impose costly communicative distortions. Distortions also can appear
as experts communicate across disciplinary boundaries, or with members of the lay public. Thus,
communicative action offers utility for avoiding unintended misunderstandings and needless conflicts. All public decisions need to achieve at least a limited degree of communicative rationality,
as every mayor knows.
TABLE 12.1
Rationality in Philosophical and Social Context
Social Context:
Philosophical Context:
Single Party
Decision Context
Multi-Party
Decision Context
Utilitarian
Perspective
(consequentialist,
optimizing,
theoretical reason)
Instrumental Rationality
(rationalize use of scarce resources,
valid facts are empirically tested,
valid values increase utility)
Strategic Rationality
(rationalize steering principles given
uncertainty, valid facts are empirically
tested, valid values increase expected utility)
Communicative
Perspective
(deontological,
consensus-seeking,
practical reason)
Instrumental Rationality
(rationalize use of scarce resources,
valid facts are empirically tested,
valid values increase utility)
Communicative Rationality
(rationalize norms for managing conflict,
valid facts enjoy consensus,
valid values enjoy consensus)
Fisher_DK3638_C012.indd 169
10/16/2006 10:49:01 AM
170
Handbook of Public Policy Analysis
Norms of ideal communication include comprehensible, sincere, legitimate, and truthful speech
(Forester 1980; Habermas 1979). A typology of communicative distortions distinguishes two dimensions: origins and intentions. Individual and unintentional distortions include poor writing or
speaking capabilities, for example. Individual and intentional distortions include such acts as lying
and deception. Systemic and unintentional distortions are due to such problems as miscommunication across disciplinary and organizational boundaries. Systemic and intentional distortions are
particularly problematic, and examples include propaganda and misleading advertising. Reducing
any of these distortions directly increases communicative rationality.
Conflicts nevertheless persist between devotees of theoretical and practical reason because the
underlying moral values differ. For the same reasons that we see the tragedy of the commons play out
in many policy domains, so we see that strategic action frequently displaces communicative action.
Individuals often have too much to gain by strategic action not to pursue it, even if it damages the
public good. Consensus has limited value in a world with great scope for independent action.
CONCLUSIONS
The desire to apply rationality to public decision making is a modern desire, bundled in with other
tenets of modernity. These include a faith that humankind is making qualitative progress, that there
is a definable “public good,” that individual actions matter, and that human inventiveness will create
more good things than bad things. These tenets are by no means universally accepted. Some see a
grimmer world in which public decision making is purely a pluralistic game, a play of power, an
unequal contest whose outcome is determined by social or economic structure, or a simple series of
do-able deals. Others see a world in which values are the only essential element of decision making,
and the factual element is secondary and perhaps even indeterminate. Rationality in public decision
making will be of little interest to partisans and demagogues, and efforts to improve the scientific
or procedural basis of public decisions are unlikely to win their support.
This chapter began by linking rationality in public decision making with science, with substance
and logic. It then added a procedural dimension that greatly enriched our notion of rationality, by
bringing in communicative and legitimacy concerns. It showed that popular tools of policy analysis
such as benefit-cost studies are deficient when judged against this broader definition of rationality; hence, better tools are under development. Rationality may even be improved by resorting to
procedural solutions such as public participation. Ultimately, rationality is a characteristic of public
decision making that some people desire some of the time. It has no guaranteed seat at the table. Its
very vulnerability should make us value it and pursue it all the more passionately.
REFERENCES
Andrews, C.J. (1992). Sorting out a consensus: Analysis in support of multi-party decisions. Environment and
Planning B: Planning and Design 19(2): 189–204.
Andrews, C.J. (2002). Humble Analysis. Westport, CT: Praeger.
Arrow, K.J. (1951). Social Choice and Individual Values. New York: John Wiley and Sons.
Axelrod, R. (1984). The Evolution of Cooperation. New York: Basic Books.
Axelrod, R. (1997). The complexity of cooperation: Agent-based models of competition and collaboration.
Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
Barnett, W.A., Chiarella, C., Keen, S., Marks, R. and Schnabl, H., eds. (2000). Commerce, Complexity, and
Evolution: Topics In Economics, Finance, Marketing and Management, Proceedings of the Twelfth
International Symposium in Economic Theory and Econometrics, International Symposia in Economic
Theory and Econometrics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Brail, R., and Klosterman, R., eds. (2001). Planning Support Systems. Redlands, CA: ESRI Press.
Fisher_DK3638_C012.indd 170
10/16/2006 10:49:01 AM
Rationality in Policy Decision Making
171
Breheny, M.J., and A.J. Hooper, eds. (1985). Rationality in Planning. London: Pion Limited.
Buchanan, J. (1965). An Economic Theory of Clubs. Econometrica 32: 1–14.
Epstein, J.M., and Axtell, R. (1996). Growing artificial societies: Social science from the bottom up. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Federal Environmental Assessment Review Office (FEARO). (1988). Public Involvement: Planning and Implementing Public Involvement Programs. Prepared by Praxis, Inc. for FEARO, Hull, Quebec, Canada.
Feiveson, H.A., Sinden, F.W., and Socolow, R.H., eds. (1976). Boundaries of Analysis: An Inquiry into the
Tocks Island Dam Controversy. Cambridge, MA: Ballinger.
Forester, J. (1980). Critical Theory and Planning Practice. APA Journal 46(3): 275–286.
Gilbert, N., and Troitzsch, K.G. (1999). Simulation for the Social Scientist. Milton Keynes: Open University
Press.
Guston, D.H. (1993). The essential tension in science and democracy. Social Epistemology 7(1): 3–23.
Habermas, J. (1979). Communication and the Evolution of Society. Boston: Beacon Press.
Jantsch, E. (1975). Design for Evolution. New York: Braziller.
Jasanoff, S. (1990). The Fifth Branch: Science Advisors as Policymakers. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University
Press.
Keeney, R., and Raiffa, H. (1976). Decisions with Multiple Objectives: Preferences and Value Tradeoffs. New
York: John Wiley.
Lindblom, C.E. (1959). The science of ‘muddling through.’ Public Administration Review 19: 78–88.
Lindblom, C.E. (1990). Inquiry and Change. New Haven: Yale University Press.
Merton, R.K. (1973.) The Normative Structure of Science. Reprinted in Merton’s The Sociology of Science.
Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Nash, J.F. (1950). Equilibrium points in N-Person Games. Proceedings of NAS.
Niskanen, W. (1971). Bureaucracy and Representative Government. Chicago: Aldine-Atherton.
Pearce, D. (1986). The MIT Dictionary of Modern Economics, entry on social welfare functions. Cambridge,
MA: MIT Press.
Sauter, V.L. (1997). Decision Support Systems. Hoboken, NJ: John Wiley and Sons.
Schelling, T.C. (1978). Micromotives and Macrobehavior. New York: W. W. Norton.
Simon, H.A. (1976). Administrative Behavior: A Study of Decision-making Processes in Administrative Organization. New York: Harper & Rowe.
Smith, G., and May, D. (1980). The Artificial Debate Between Rationalist and Incrementalist Models of
Decision-Making. Policy and Politics 8: 147–161.
Susskind, L., and Elliott, M. (1983). Paternalism, Conflict, and Coproduction. New York: Plenum Press.
Teitelbaum, D. (1998). An Adaptive Agent Approach to Environmental Regulation. Ph.D. disseratation, Pittsburgh, PA: Carnegie Mellon University.
Toumey, C.P. (1996) Conjuring Science. New Brunswick, NJ: Rutgers University Press.
Tversky, A., and Kahneman, D. (1974). Judgment under uncertainty: Heuristics and biases. Science 185:1124–
1131.
von Neumann, J., and Morgenstern, O. (1944). Theory of Games and Economic Behavior. Princeton, NJ:
Princeton University Press.
Wallace, W. (1971). The Logic of Science in Sociology. New York: Aldine deGruyter.
Weber, M. (1922, 1957.) The Theory of Social and Economic Organization. New York: Free Press.
Webler, T., and Renn, O. (1995). A brief primer on participation: philosophy and practice. In O. Renn, T.
Webler and P. Wiedemann, eds. Fairness and Competence in Citizen Participation. Dordrecht: Kluwer
Academic Publishers, pp. 17–33 (Ch. 2).
Wengert, N. (1976). Citizen Participation: Practice in Search of a Theory. In A. Utton, ed., Natural Resources
for a Democratic Society. Boulder, CO: Westview Press, pp. 1–40.
Fisher_DK3638_C012.indd 171
10/16/2006 10:49:01 AM
Fisher_DK3638_C012.indd 172
10/16/2006 10:49:02 AM