Bạn đang xem bản rút gọn của tài liệu. Xem và tải ngay bản đầy đủ của tài liệu tại đây (31.76 MB, 351 trang )
OBSCENITY A S PORNOGRAPH Y 13
9
reducing "psychic distance," even when moral sensibility is not involved. I
shall consider these distinct factors in turn.
The word "obscene" is commonly applied to behavior thought to be
immoral. When we use the word in this way, we do not reserve it necessarily for what we consider the most immoral behavior; secret, devious, or
subtle private immoralities, no matter how seriously wrong they may seem
to be, are rarely called "obscene" at all. (But see Chapter 10, note 25, p.
297.) Rather, we think of those immoralities that are absolutely open and
shameless, and therefore "shocking" or "disgusting," as the typically obscene ones. The word "obscene" emphasizes how shocking they are to
behold, as well as how flagrant they are as departures from a moral norm.
Thus utterly cynical, obvious, or brazen falsehoods told with amazing
aplomb before observers who know that they are intentional, are "obscene
lies" even when they are only moderate departures from the moral norm. It
is typically the grossly obtrusive offense to sensibility that elicits judgments
of obscenity, whether the sensibility in question be moral, religious, patriotic, or merely gustatory or sensory.
Naturally enough, persons who hold certain moral convictions about
sexual conduct will find blatantly obtrusive exhibitions or depictions of
tabooed sexuality obscene, not simply because they violate moral standards
but because they do so openly and blatantly. Given that such is the case,
the sensibilities of these persons would command the respect, and, if only
other things were equal, the protection, of the law.
This account, however, is still too vague to allay the puzzlement that
generated this psychological inquiry. Hardly anyone holds the conviction
that al l sexual behavior as such is wrong, whatever the circumstances and
whoever the actors. At most, people find illicit or unlicensed sex, sex out of
marriage, solitary sex, or sex at inappropriate times and places to be immoral. Yet many people find the depiction or explicit description of any sexual
conduct at all, licit or illicit, to be obscene. How then could the obscenity
stem from the perceived violation of moral principle?
The answer, I suspect, must employ the distinction between what i s
depicted, which is not thought to be obscene, at least not on moral grounds,
and th e act of depicting it , which may under the circumstances be a blatantly
offensive violation of moral norms. What is immoral (by the standards of
some offended parties) in vivid depictions or unvarnished descriptions of
the sex acts of real or fictitious persons, even when those acts in the depicted circumstances are entirely licit, are the "impure thoughts" in the
minds of the beholders, which are in large part "desires in the imagination"
for what would be immoral if realized. When the beholder finds the depiction obscene (on this account), he finds his own spontaneous concupiscence
140 OFFENS
E T O OTHER S
disgusting, and it quickly curdles into shame and revulsion; or, if the beholder is part of a group, he or she may think of the inevitably impure ideas
in the minds of the others as repugnant, or may take the act of showing or
describing sex as itself immoral insofar as it is meant to exploit the weakness
of the audience and induce impure thoughts in receptive minds. So it is not
that what is depicted is thought to be immoral, but rather that the act of
depicting it in those circumstances, and the spectacle of its common perception, with those motives, intentions, and likely effects, is thought to be
immoral and—because the immorality is shameless and open—obscene.
The second explanation of how sex can come to seem obscene has nothing to do with anyone's conception of morality. Even persons who utterly
reject the prevailing sexual taboos may find some sexual depictions offensive to the point of obscenity. The reactions of such persons are to be
sharply contrasted with those of people with prudish moral sensibilities
who get trapped between their own salaciousness and shame. The disgust
of this second group is not moral disgust. Rather, it is the spontaneous
revulsion to what is overpoweringly close that is commonly produced not
only by crude pornography but by other kinds of experiences as well.
George P. Elliott has diagnosed the phenomenon well:
Psychologically, the trouble with [artless] pornography is that, in our culture
at least, it offends the sense of separateness, of individuality, of privacy . . .
We have a certain sense of speeialness about those voluntary bodily functions
each must perform for himself—bathing, eating, defecating, urinating, copulating—Take eating, for example. There are few strong taboos around the act of
eating; yet most people feel uneasy about being the only one at the table who is
or who is not, eating, and there is an absolute difference between eating a rare
steak washed down by plenty of red wine and watching a close-up movie of
someone doing so. One wishes to draw back when one is actually or imaginatively too close to the mouth of a man enjoying his dinner; in exactly the same
way one wishes to remove oneself from the presence of man and woman
enjoying sexual intercourse. 27
"Not to withdraw," Elliott adds, "is to peep, to pervert looking so that it
becomes a sexual end in itself.'"8 Here he makes a different point and a less
tenable one. The point is (or should be) that if we are going to look without
being disgusted, we had better look from a proper distance, not that looking
at all is a "perversion". Not only erotically realistic art but also artful
pornography ca n satisfy the criterion of distance, and when it does we
identify imaginatively with one of the parties whom we watch rather than
thinking of ourselves as intrusive third parties or embarrassed "peepers."
Pornographers whose aim is aphrodisiac rather than emetic might well
consult Elliott for good tips. He tells us, with convincing examples, how
the problem of distance is solved in pictorial art, while implying that the
OBSCENITY AS PORNOGRAPHY
141
same solutions must be forever unavailable to the pornographer, but that is
because he identifies pornography quite arbitrarily with the gross and artless kind. Distance is preserved in erotic pictorial art through the use of
artificial stylized images, as in the throngs of erotic statues on Indian
temples, by making the erotic image small, or by sketching it in with only a
few details:
One does not want to be close to a man while he is defecating nor to have a
close-up picture of him in that natural, innocent act—not at all because defecating is reprehensible, only because it is displeasing to intrude upon. One would
much rather have a detailed picture of a thief stealing the last loaf of bread from a
starving widow with three children than one of Albert Schweitzer at stool.
However, Brueghel's painting "The Netherlandish Proverbs" represents two
bare rear ends sticking out of a window, presumably of people defecating into
the river below, and one quite enjoys the sight—because it is a small part of a
large and pleasant picture of the world and because the two figures are tiny,
sketched in, far away. 29
What should we say—or, more to the point, what should the law say—
about those persons whose psyches are not accurately described by Elliott,
persons with special kinky tastes who prefer their psychic distances short
and their sexual perceptions large and detailed? Tiny Gulliver (as Elliott
reminds us) is "revolted by every blemish on the breast of the Brobdingnagian wet nurse suckling the baby." 30 Even though the breast was pleasingly
shaped and would have been delightful to behold had its proportions been
suited to persons of Gulliver's size, it extended six feet from the nurse's
body and its nipple was "half the size of a man's head." Swift makes his
point well, and most readers are appalled in their imaginations, but what
are we to say of the special reader who is sexually excited by the very
thought of this normally emetic object? The law, of course, should say
nothing at all, provided that satisfaction of the quirky taste is not achieved
at the cost of direct offense to unwilling observers.
The more interesting point, however, is that the overwhelming majority
of people do not enjoy being spatially or psychologically close to the physiological organs and processes deemed "private" in our culture. To revel in
these objects is about as common a pastime, I should think, as reveling in
the slinky, smelly things that most of us find immediately repellant to the
senses and thus in an analogous way obscene.
Our discussion of the relation between (judgmental) obscenity and pornography can now be summarized. Obscenity and pornography are entirely
distinct concepts that overlap in their applications to the world but by no
means coincide. Obscene things are those that are apt to offend people by
142
OFFENSE TO OTHERS
eliciting such reactions as disgust, shock, and repugnance. Moreover, when
we call something obscene we usually wish to endorse some form of offense
as the appropriate reaction to it. Pornography, on the other hand, simply
consists of all those pictures, plays, books, and films whose raison d'etre is
that they are erotically arousing. Some obscene things (e.g., dirty words
and insulting gestures) are not pornographic. Indeed some obscene things
have nothing whatever to do with sex. Human wastes and other disgusting
objects fall into that subcategory of the obscene, as do acts of rejoicing in
the misfortunes of others, racial slurs, shameless lies, and other blatant but
nonsexual immoralities. Some pornographic things, for example artful
paintings, are not obscene. Others, such as close-up, highly magnified photographs of sexual couplings are obscene, though their very obscenity tends
to defeat their pornographic purpose.
In the absence of convincing evidence of its causal tie to social harms,
pornography ought to be prohibited by law only when it is obscene and
then precisely because it is obscene. But obscenity (extreme offensiveness)
is only a necessary condition, not a sufficient condition, for rightful prohibition. In addition, the offending conduct must not be reasonably avoidable, and the risk of offense must not have been voluntarily assumed by the
beholders. (No doubt additional conditions might also be added such as, for
example, that reasonable efforts have been made to exclude children.)
The defining purposes of plotted fiction and dramatic literature cannot be
satisfied by a work that is also properly denominated pornographic. On the
other hand, there is no contradiction in the idea of a pornographic painting,
musical composition, or (perhaps) poem. But the question whether or not
art can be pornographic, while obviously important for American constitutional law, which places limits on what legislatures may do, is of less interest to critical public policy, which asks what legislatures ought to do from
among the alternative courses permitted them. The Supreme Court has
interpreted the first amendment as permitting legislatures to prohibit all
obscenity that is not also art (or opinion). 3 ' Reasonable liberty-limiting
principles also give special importance to works of art but prevent legislatures from prohibiting even obscene non-art provided that it is not imposed
on unwilling audiences. It is quite unnecessary to determine whether (or to
what degree) a given book or film is also art, when the only people who
experience it are either unoffended or have voluntarily assumed the risk of
offense in advance.
Finally, we considered how sexual conduct could possibly seem obscene
to anyone, given the universal human propensity to derive extreme pleasure
from it. Those who find pornography obscene, we concluded, do so either
when it is done in circumstances that render it (by their standards) both
OBSCENITY A S PORNOGRAPH Y 14
3
immoral and blatantly and shamelessly obtrusive and thus shocking to moral sensibility, or else when it has reduced psychic distance to the threshold
of repugnance or disgust, even when no moral considerations are involved.
7. Th e feminist case against pornography^ 2
In recent years a powerful attack on pornography has been made from a
different quarter and on different, but often shifting grounds. Until 1970 or
so, the demand for legal restraints on pornography came mainly from "sexual conservatives," those who regarded the pursuit of erotic pleasure for its
own sake to be immoral or degrading, and its public depiction obscene. The
new attack, however, comes not from prudes and bluenoses, but from
women who have been in the forefront of the sexual revolution. We do not
hear any of the traditional complaints about pornography from this group—
that erotic states in themselves are immoral, that sexual titillation corrupts
character, and that the spectacle of "appeals to prurience" is repugnant to
moral sensibility. The new charge is rather that pornography degrades,
abuses, and defames women, and contributes to a general climate of attitudes toward women that makes violent sex crimes more frequent. Pornography, they claim, has come to pose a threat to public safety, and its legal
restraint can find justification either under the harm principle, or, by analogy with Nazi parades in Skokie and K.K.K. rallies, on some theory of
profound (and personal) offense.
It is somewhat misleading to characterize the feminist onslaught as a new
argument, or new emphasis in argument, against the same old thing. By the
19605 pornography itself had become in large measure a new and uglier
kind of phenomenon. There had always been sado-masochistic elements in
much pornography, and a small minority taste to be served with concentrated doses of it. There had also been more or less prominent expressions
of contemptuous attitudes toward abject female "sex objects," even in much
relatively innocent pornography. But now a great wave of violent pornography appears to have swept over the land, as even the mass circulation porno
magazines moved beyond the customary nude cheesecake and formula
stories, to explicit expressions of hostility to women, and to covers and
photographs showing "women and children abused, beaten, bound, and
tortured" apparently "for the sexual titillation of consumers."" When the
circulation of the monthly porn magazines comes to 16 million and the
porno industry as a whole does $4 billion a year in business, the new trend
cannot help but be alarming.34
There is no necessity, however, that pornography as such be degrading to
women. First of all, we can imagine easily enough an ideal pornography in
144 OFFENS
E T O OTHER S
which men and women are depicted enjoying their joint sexual pleasures in
ways that show not a trace of dominance or humiliation of either party by
the other.35 The materials in question might clearly satisfy my previous
definition of "pornography" as materials designed entirely and effectively to
induce erotic excitement in observers, without containing any of the extraneous sexist elements. Even if we confine our attention to actual specimens
of pornography—and quite typical ones—we find many examples where
male dominance and female humiliation are not present at all. Those of us
who were budding teenagers in the 19305 and '408 will tend to take as our
model of pornography the comic strip pamphlets in wide circulation among
teenagers during that period. The characters were all drawn from the popular legitimate comic strips—The Gumps, Moon Mullins, Maggie and Jiggs,
etc.—and were portrayed in cartoons that were exact imitations of the
originals. In the pornographic strips, however, the adventures were all
erotic. Like all pornography, the cartoons greatly exaggerated the size of
organs and appetites, and the "plot lines" were entirely predictable. But the
episodes were portrayed with great good humor, a kind of joyous feast of
erotica in which the blessedly unrepressed cartoon figures shared with perfect equality. Rather than being humiliated or dominated, the women characters equalled the men in their sheer earthy gusto. (That feature especially
appealed to teenage boys who could only dream of unrestrained female
gusto.) The episodes had no butt at all except prudes and hypocrites. Most
of us consumers managed to survive with our moral characters intact.
In still other samples of actual pornography, there is indeed the appearance of male dominance and female humiliation, but even in many of these,
explanations of a more innocent character are available. It is in the nature of
fantasies, especially adolescent fantasies, whether erotic or otherwise, to
glorify imaginatively, in excessive and unrealistic ways, the person who
does the fantasizing. When that person is a woman and the fantasy is
romantic, she may dream of herself surrounded by handsome lovesick suitors, or in love with an (otherwise) magnificent man who is prepared to
throw himself at her feet, worship the ground she walks on, go through hell
for her if necessary—the cliches pile up endlessly. If the fantasizing person
is a man and his reverie is erotic, he may dream of women who worship the
ground h e walks on, etc., and would do anything for the honor of making
love with him, and who having sampled his unrivaled sexual talents would
grovel at his feet for more, etc., etc. The point of the fantasy is self-adulation, not "hostility" toward the other sex.
Still other explanations may be available. "Lust," wrote Norman Mailer,
"is a world of bewildering dimensions . . ."3
hold of the imagination, it is likely to be accompanied by almost any images
OBSCENITY A S PORNOGRAPH Y 14
5
suggestive of limitiessness, any natural accompaniments of explosive unrestrained passion. Not only men but women too have been known to scratch
or bite (like house cats) during sexual excitement, and the phrase "I could
hug you to pieces"—a typical expression of felt "limitiessness"—is normally
taken as an expression of endearment, not of homicidal fury. Sexual passion
in the male animal (there is as yet little but conjecture on this subject) may
be associated at deep instinctive or hormonal levels with the states that
capture the body and mind during aggressive combat. Some such account
may be true of a given man, and explain why a certain kind of pornography
may arouse him, without implying anything at all about his settled attitudes
toward women, or his general mode of behavior toward them. Then, of
course, it is a commonplace thai: many "normal" people, both men and
women, enjoy sado-masochistic fantasies from time to time, without effect
on character or conduct. Moreover, there are pornographic materials intended for men, that appeal to their masochistic side exclusively, in which
they are "ravished" and humiliated by some grim-faced amazon of fearsome
dimensions. Great art these materials are not, but neither are they peculiarly degrading to women.
It will not do then to isolate the most objectionable kinds of pornography,
the kinds that are most offensive and even dangerous to women, and reserve
the label "pornographic" for them alone. This conscious redefinition is what
numerous feminist writers have done, however, much to the confusion of
the whole discussion. Gloria Stcinem rightly protests against "the truly
obscene idea that sex and the domination of women must be combined"37
(there is a proper use of the word "obscene"), but then she manipulates
words so that it becomes true by definition (hence merely trivially true) that
all pornography is obscene in this fashion. She notes that "pornography"
stems from the Greek root meaning "prostitutes" or "female captives,"
"thus letting us know that the subject is not mutual love, or love at all, but
domination and violence against women." 38 Steinem is surely right that the
subject of the stories, pictures, and films that have usually been called
"pornographic" is not love, but it doesn't follow that they are all without
exception about male domination over women either. Of course Steinem
doesn't make that further claim as a matter of factual reporting, but as a
stipulated redefinition. Her proposal can lead other writers to equivocate,
however, and find sexist themes in otherwise innocent erotica that have
hitherto been called "pornographic"—simply because they ar e naturally
called by that name. Steinem adopts "erotica" as the contrasting term to
"pornography" as redefined. Erotica, she concludes, is about sexuality, but
"pornography is about power, and sex-as-a-wcapon," conquerors dominating victims. The distinction is a real one, but better expressed in such terms
146
OFFENSE TO OTHERS
as "degrading pornography" (Steinem's "pornography") as opposed to
"other pornography" (Steinem's "erotica").
At least one other important distinction must be made among the miscellany of materials in the category of degrading pornography. Some degrading pornography is also violent, glorifying in physical mistreatment of the
woman, and featuring "weapons of torture or bondage, wounds and
bruises."39 "One frightening spread from Chic Magazine showed a series of
pictures of a woman covered with blood, masturbating with a knife. The
title was 'Columbine Cuts Up'."4° A movie called "Snuff" in which female
characters (and, it is alleged, the actresses who portrayed them) are tortured
to death for the sexual entertainment of the audiences, was shown briefly in
a commercial New York theatre. The widely circulated monthly magazine
Hustler once had a cover picture of a nude woman being pushed head first
into a meat grinder, her shapely thighs and legs poised above the opening to
the grinder in a sexually receptive posture, while the rest comes out of the
bottom as ground meat. The exaggeration of numbers in Kathleen Barry's
chilling description hardly blunts its horror: "In movie after movie women
are raped, ejaculated on, urinated on, anally penetrated, beaten, and, with
the advent of snuff films, murdered in an orgy of sexual pleasure."4' The
examples, alas, are abundant and depressing.
There are other examples, however, of pornography that is degrading to
women but does not involve violence. Gloria Steinem speaks of more subtle
forms of coercion: "a physical attitude of conqueror and victim, the use of
race or class difference to imply the same thing, perhaps a very unequal
nudity with one person exposed and vulnerable while the other is clothed."42
As the suggested forms of coercion become more and more subtle, obviously
there will be very difficult line-drawing problems for any legislature brave
enough to enter this area.
Yet the most violent cases at one end of the spectrum are as clear as they
can be. They all glory in wanton and painful violence against helpless
victims and do this with the extraordinary intention (sometimes even successful) of causing sexual arousal in male viewers. One could give every
other form of pornography, degrading or not, the benefit of the doubt, and
still identify with confidence all members of the violent extreme category.
If there is a strong enough argument against pornography to limit the
liberty of pornographers, it is probably restricted to this class of materials.
Some feminist writers speak as if that would not be much if any restriction,
but that may be a consequence of their defining pornography in terms of its
most revolting specimens.43 A pornographic story or film may be degrading
in Steinem's subtle sense, in that it shows an intelligent man with a stupid
woman, or a wealthy man with a chambermaid, and intentionally exploits
OBSCENITY AS PORNOGRAPH Y
147
the inequality for the sake of the .special sexual tastes of the presumed male
consumer, but if that were the only way in which the work degraded
women, it would fall well outside the extreme (violent) category. All the
more so, stories in which the male and female are equals—and these materials too can count as pornographic—would fall outside the objectionable
category.
May the law legitimately be used to restrict the liberty of pornographers
to produce and distribute, and their customers to purchase and use, erotic
materials that are violently abusive of women? (I am assuming that no
strong case can be made for the proscription of materials that are merely
degrading in one of the relatively subtle and nonviolent ways.) Many feminists answer, often with reluctance, in the affirmative. Their arguments can
be divided into two general classes. Some simply invoke the harm principle.
Violent pornography wrongs and harms women, according to these arguments, either by defaming them as a group, or (more importantly) byinciting males to violent crimes against them or creating a cultural climate
in which such crimes are likely to become more frequent. Th e two traditional legal categories involved in these harm-principle arguments, then, are
defamation and incitement. The other class of arguments invoke the offense
principle, not in order to prevent mere "nuisances," but to prevent profound offense analogous to that of the Jews in Skokie or the blacks in a
town where the K.K.K. rallies.
8. Violent pornography, the cult of macho,
and harm to women
I shall not spend much time on the claim that violent and other extremely
degrading pornography should be banned on the ground that it defames
women. In a skeptical spirit, I can begin by pointing out that there are
immense difficulties in applying the civil law of libel and slander as it is
presently constituted in such a way as not to violate freedom of expression.
Problems with criminal libel and slander would be even more unmanageable,
and group defamation, whether civil or criminal, would multiply the problems still further. The argument on the other side is that pornography is
essentially propaganda—propaganda against women. It does not slander
women in the technical legal sense by asserting damaging falsehoods about
them, because it asserts nothing at all. But it spreads an image of women as
mindless playthings or "objects," inferior beings fit only to be used and
abused for the pleasure of men, whether they like it or not, but often to their
own secret pleasure. This picture lowers the esteem men have for women,
and for that reason (if defamation is the basis of the argument) is sufficient
148
OFFENSE T O OTHERS
ground for proscription even in the absence of any evidence of tangible harm
to women caused by the behavior of misled and deluded men.
If degrading pornography defames (libels or slanders) women, it must be
in virtue of some beliefs about women-—false beliefs—that it conveys, so
that in virtue of those newly acquired or reenforced false beliefs, consumers
lower their esteem for women in general. If a work of pornography, for
example, shows a woman (or group of women) in exclusively subservient or
domestic roles, that may lead the consumer to believe that women, in virtue
of some inherent female characteristics, are only fit for such roles. There is
no doubt that much pornography does portray women in subservient positions, but if that is defamatory to women in anything like the legal sense,
then so are soap commercials on TV. So are many novels, even some good
ones. (A good novel may yet be about some degraded characters.) That
some groups are portrayed in unflattering roles has not hitherto been a
ground for the censorship of fiction or advertising. Besides, it is not clearly
the group that is portrayed at all in such works, but only one individual (or
small set of individuals) and fictitious ones at that. Are fat men defamed by
Shakespeare's picture of Falstaff? Are Jews defamed by the characterization
of Shylock? Could any writer today even hope to write a novel partly about
a fawning corrupted black, under group defamation laws, without risking
censorship or worse? The chilling effect on the practice of fiction-writing
would amount to a near freeze.
Moreover, as Fred Berger points out,44 the degrading images and defamatory beliefs pornographic works are alleged to cause are not produced in the
consumer by explicit statements asserted with the intent to convince the
reader or auditor of their truth. Rather they are caused by the stimulus of
the work, in the context, on the expectations, attitudes, and beliefs the
viewer brings with him to the work. That is quite other than believing an
assertion on the authority or argument of the party making the assertion, or
understanding the assertion in the first place in virtue of fixed conventions
of language use and meaning. Without those fixed conventions of language,
the work has to be interpreted in order for any message to be extracted
from it, and the process of interpretation, as Berger illustrates abundantly,
is "always a matter of judgment and subject to great variation among
persons."45 What looks like sexual subservience to some looks like liberation
from sexual repression to others. It is hard to imagine how a court could
provide a workable, much less fair, test of whether a given work has sufficiently damaged male esteem toward women for it to be judged criminally
defamatory, when so much of the viewer's reaction he brings on himself,
and viewer reactions are so •widely variable.
It is not easy for a single work to defame successfully a group as large as